The Social Exchange and Choice Framework - PART 2

We have been following Nye's (1979) version of exchange
theory, but
it is important to note the diversity within exchange theories. We
it is important to note the diversity within exchange theories. We

classify the many variants on the basis of
whether they are microsocial or macrosocial. You may recall
that a microsocial theory includes the assumption that the individual is the
active unit of analysis, whereas in macrosocial theories the
active unit of analysis is the social group or institution.
Although all theorists would like to think that they have successfully
bridged the chasm between micro- and macroperspectives,
there are in reality few theories for which one can confidently make such a claim. Individual exchange
theories usually involve simply adding
up all the individual motivations and calling that group motivation or developing a "great man" theory
whereby one actor is responsible for
social change and therefore only one motive
need be analyzed (Homans, 1967). Macroexchange theories examine the exchanges between groups and the resulting
social solidarity and alliance
formation. Individuals are largely lost in the larger social group and in most ways unidentifiable and
unrecoverable as part of an
explanation.
MICROEXCHANGE
THEORIES

Another example of a microexchange variant is
the theoretical work of Emerson (1976), dealing
with the relative balance, or ratio,
of rewards in social relationships. His unit of
analysis is the relationship rather than the individual. His
microsocial approach might be suitable to the
study of the family, but there has as .yet not been any research applications of his work directed specifically at studying
families.
One of the more important variants of
exchange theory used to study family, relationships is equity theory. Although equity theory is
directly derived from exchange theory
propositions, it contains the additional proposition that fair
exchanges are more profitable to relationships
than are unfair exchanges. If A and B are in an unfair relationship, then the social norm of reciprocity is not
maintained, and the relationship is likely to
be discontinued by one of its members. Thus,
whenever a relationship provides profitable outcomes, it is essential for the maintenance of the relationship that
exchanges be equitable. One can immediately see
how equity might be applied to exchanges between marital partners
and in family relations. Indeed, family
scholars have used equity theory to study such longer-term family relationships (e.g., Scanzoni, 1972; Sexton &
Perlman, 1989; Walster & Walster, 1978). It is interesting to note that
several investigators of equity in marriage
(e.g., Pina & Bengtson, 1993; Sexton & Perlman,
1989) have concluded that, at best, equity appears to have restricted explanatory value for marital relations.








riEURIES Social Exchange and Choice 9•7
have already reviewed. First, most macroexchange
theorists identify two types of exchanges: restricted and generalized exchanges. Restricted
exchanges take place at one point in time and involve little trust. For example, when you buy something in a store,
you hand money to the salesperson, who then
gives you the item you have selected. On the other hand,
generalized exchanges take place over a longer
period of time and therefore require more trust. An example of a generalized exchange is lending money to a friend or
relative and trusting that repayment will be
made at some future date. The trust required
in generalized exchanges is buttressed by the norm of reciprocity as
discussed above in regard to equity theory. That individuals find the relationships in a family group profitable
is in part because the family group maintains
profitable exchanges with other social
organizations such as schools, churches, and the economy. The essence of macroexchange perspectives is the view that
these group and organizational exchanges are
more central than individual decision
making.
In structural exchange theories, the individual's choices
are viewed as being determined by the
macroexchanges between group and organizations. Note that this is just the
opposite of the view in microexchange theories
such as rational choice theory that the individual's decisions determine the group's exchanges.
Perhaps the best example of macroexchange thinking applied
to the family is provided by the work of the
French structuralist Claude Levi-Strauss (1969), who developed
a theory that the fabric of societies is
constructed by norms that require generalized social exchanges between groups. At the heart of these generalized
exchanges are the exchanges between kin groups and clans. Prescriptive mating
norms require the formation of alliances
between groups through the exchange of mates. For example, in
a moiety, or two-clan system, if you are a
member of the Bear clan and want to form a political, social, and economic alliance with the Eagle clan, you could create
a mating rule such as, Bear women must
marry Eagle men. The strongest expression of this alliance rule
would be a totemic incest taboo, for example,
forbidding an Eagle man to marry an Eagle woman. LeviStrauss's (1969) work has been criticized as not being
applicable to voluntary mate selection systems
such as our own, but his work has led to
some interesting applications, such as Harrison White's (1963) book examining mathematical models of kinship. In general,
the more macrosocial utilitarian theories
have not been applied to the family as a unit of analysis but rather to larger
kinship groups such as clans. As a
result, North American family scholars have tended to favor the more microsocial variants of utilitarian thinking.







One way to understand a theory is to apply it to some
examples. In this section, we apply exchange
theory to two areas of research in the study of
the family: divorce and sexual relations.
DIVORCE





rewards and costs (profit) associated with possibilities
other than marriage, for example, being
single and divorced. Among the possible costs to
this alternative would be child support, alimony, peer disapproval, the church's disapproval, kinship group
disapproval, sexual deprivation, loss of interaction
with one's children, role loss, and so on. Some
of the possible rewards might be finding a more compatible partner, freeing family members from a confrontational
and conflict-ridden home life, and freeing
oneself from family responsibilities. The computation
of the perceived alternatives to marriage depends on a diversity of variables, such as the gender ratio of the
community in which one lives and the ages of
one's children.
George Levinger (1965, 1966) assessed the likelihood of
divorce in terms of
"attractions," "barriers," and "alternatives." If
attractions to one's spouse and barriers to
divorce are both low, and if alternatives are
attractive, then divorce is more likely. Because all three factors are important, it is not sufficient to explain divorce in
terms of any one of them alone. This application should
remind us that it is important to know if
the subjective calculations of both partners must be taken into account. Is divorce more likely if only one partner
perceives a "poor deal" by staying married, or
must both partners be getting a "poor deal"?
In some societies, it may not be possible for one partner to end the
relationship unilaterally if the other partner is unwilling to do so. Thus, when applying the exchange perspective to divorce,
we need to specify the conditions under which
miserable spouses can be expected to stay
married.
One of the major stumbling blocks for successfully
applying this exchange theory explanation to
divorce is that the rewards and costs in the
two comparison levels seem to change over the life span of the individual. This is evident in the paradoxical finding
pointed out by White and Booth (1991) that the
great bulk of divorces (30%-40%) occur in
the first S years of marriage, the very point in the life span that is
associated with the highest marital satisfaction. Furthermore, as marital satisfaction declines over the life course, so
does the risk of divorce. It seems a paradox that we
should find the greatest number of
divorces when marriages are the happiest! However, the comparison levels for
happiness are highest early in a relationship, and it is easier to become disappointed when expectations are not
fulfilled.











GENDER DIFFERENCES IN SEXUAL
BEHAVIOR
Our second application of exchange theory is drawn from
propositions presented by Nye (1979) regarding sexual behavior, although we focus not on the formal propositions but on what the
explanation would look like. But first, what
is it that we want to explain about gender
differences in sexual behavior? In most, if not all, cultures, sex seems more actively sought after by males than females.
Although there may exist a biological answer to
why this is the case (see Chapter 8), most
authors assume that the biological drive is malleable in how it is satisfied. Furthermore, many of the behaviors that could
be associated with a higher sex drive in one
gender, such as prostitution, are usually labeled
social rather than biological problems.
Nye (1979) argues that males are more likely to exchange
rewards (especially money or marriage) for
sexual access. Because exchange theory
is essentially a motivational theory, Nye posits that sex is more profitable for males than it is for females. Nye is not
assuming a more vital sex drive for males than
females. Such an assumption would place the
entire explanation on the shoulders of the biological importance, or salience,
of sex for males over females. As a social scientist, Nye seems to assume that the biological drive for the two
genders is equal and he therefore searches
for a social explanation.

women. Men are more likely to
achieve orgasm than are women, and
women are more likely to experience frustration from sexual relations.
The result of these differential
costs and rewards is that relative to women,
men, in general, find that sex offers greater rewards and fewer costs. As a result, men must either have sexual
relations with those who find it as rewarding as they do (homosexuality) or
they must increase the rewards for women.
Nye says that the usual ways in which these
rewards are increased for women is for men to offer either money or the
probability of marriage. Other rewards, such as status and security, might be more salient at various points in the
life course.
Nye's application of exchange has
great scope and breadth. For example, it could explain female
adornment as a sexual attractor that functions
to increase the value of the exchange. Because married persons have already struck a bargain, we would expect
much less difference between men and women in postmarital sexual relations. This prediction is consistent with the fact that a
difference of less than 10% exists between male and
female extramarital affairs (Blumstein & Schwartz,
1983). Furthermore, we can make some general predictions, such as that when the costs of contraception
(inconvenience and medical complications) are
equally distributed among both genders and
sexual knowledge is shared among both genders so that both genders enjoy the same level of outcome, then we would
expect less sexual bargaining with marriage
and money. Keep in mind that Nye's (1979) theory remains to be tested and must be shown to provide
a better explanation than competing theories, but this example does illustrate exchange
theory's potential breadth of explanation.
|
Implications for Intervention
Exchange theory has numerous
implications for family policy, treatment,
and intervention. We can only sketch a few of these to give the flavor of the richness of this theory for application to
family issues.
One of the most influential
applications of the theory is in the area
of intervention and prevention in marital and parent—child interactions. This application has largely been
constructed on the view that parent—child and husband—wife relations
represent behavioral exchanges. Gerald Patterson and his associates at the Oregon Research Institute pioneered this approach (Patterson &
Reid, 1970). Currently, many scholars and practitioners use the behavioral
exchange approach. For example, Bagarozzi (1993) suggests that in designing
behavioral contracts with spouses,
therapists should focus on increasing positive or
rewarding behaviors and decreasing negative behavioral exchanges.
|
Clearly, such an intervention
would increase the profitability of the
marital relationship. Markman and his colleagues developed the Prevention and Relationship Enhancement Program for
enhancing marriages and decreasing divorce
based on the notion that distressed couples
seem to enter a reciprocal exchange of negative behaviors (e.g., Renick, Blumberg, & Markman, 1992). Although
these authors view their program as
empirically based rather than founded on exchange
theory, the basic interpretive notion of behavioral exchanges remains true to the exchange perspective.
Another area of application for
the theory is in the area of family policy. Haveman and Wolfe (1994),
following Becker (1981), take a human
capital, or rational choice, approach to child welfare and education 0-11'4. They view parents, schools, and
government as making investments in the human capital
of our children. To the extent that we
invest unwisely or in a miserly fashion, we reap the failures of succeeding generations and social problems such as crime
and economic dependence. Haveman and Wolfe
(1994) review the relative costs of geographic
moves, parental separation, and several other variables on the eventual success of children. These costs are seen
as our inability to invest wisely in the human
capital of tomorrow's generation and society.
Haveman and Wolfe's Succeeding
Generations is one of the clearest
applications of economic exchange principles to the interpretation of family data and the framing of family policy.
Critiques and Discussion
Our focus in this section is on
the criticisms commonly directed at microexchange
theories. We recognize that each of the criticisms discussed is more applicable to some microsocial
variants than others. Our central target must be the
general notions presented above and principally
derived from Nye (1979). One caveat should be mentioned: No social theory solves all the problems we raise in
our critiques. Our criticism is not aimed at
convincing the theorist or the student that one
theory is better than another. Rather, these critiques are intended to illuminate the choices we make in adopting a
theoretical stance and to point out the 'areas that are
in need of more creative thinking by the next
generation of scholars.
As we mentioned at the beginning,
microsocial exchange theories are
usually based on methodological
individualism, the assumption that
the individual is the appropriate unit to study to gain an understanding of the family. As far as we know, there has
never been a definition of the family as
simply an aggregation of individuals. Yet,
|
when we take the individual's ratio of rewards and costs
as the basis of our theory about families, we
are assuming that the aggregation of individual
members is the family. Theoretically, this would make the family no different from any other collection of actors.
Yet the family has characteristics that seem
unlike other social groups. For most of us, our
families are lifelong social groups that we enter by birth and leave by death. Our families have roles that are unlike
work group roles, such as filial obligations
toward the parents. And our families have
biological and social relations (blood and marriage) that are unlike those in any other social group. Thus, to assume
that individual actors are interchangeable and
that families as social groups can be explained
by the motivation of individuals seems problematic.
Explaining social order poses a problem for all the forms
of utilitarianism. If we view explanation as
emanating from individual motivation, then it is usually
difficult to demonstrate how we developed social
norms and social institutions. Although most microsocial theorists include a discussion of the norm of reciprocity
(you should help those that help you), it is
much less clear how this norm is derived
from individual self-interest. In addition, in analyzing costs and rewards, theorists readily accept the given nature of
social norms and institutions without indicating
how these are explained by the theory. For instance, in weighing
the rewards and costs of not wearing
clothing on a hot summer day, you automatically take into account formal norms
(laws) and informal norms. Most of you recognize
that no matter how rewarding you might find going without clothing, there are strong formal and informal
norms that constrain your behavior. The major
answer utilitarians have given this question
regarding social order is known as the social
contract. There are many variants of this idea, but
basically it involves the assumption that
individuals band together and form a social order so as to have security of person and property. This social contract
implies that some individual freedom is relinquished
so that order may be maintained. But this
view, although admitting the importance and power of social institutions, largely begs the question of how these
social institutions evolve and change. Clearly, most of
you have no recollection of relinquishing some of your freedoms
in exchange for order. Rather, you were socialized by institutions
to be on time, to behave in certain ways,
and to expect formal and informal sanctions if you transgressed the social order.
Another
problematic area for microsocial exchange theory is altruistic
behavior. Many times we see (and praise) behaviors that seem
to be characterized by the individual giving up rewards and suffering
costs so that others may prosper. Some simple examples are
a soldier giving up his or her life in combat or a mother
running into a burning house to save her child.
Exchange theorists would point out that this is a problem of attribution or
inference. All we have really observed is the behavior (and not
the motive), and we incorrectly attribute an other-directedness to an act that
was actually calculated to yield profit. Thus, the mother
is acting in the least costly way if she regards
the death of her child as more costly than the personal risk she incurs by her attempt to save the child. The soldier who
refuses to fight faces court martial,
humiliation, and.shame. On the other hand, critics
might argue that these people are not acting rationally at all,



the family.
One of the most basic questions in the study of the
family is "Why do people have children?"
Exchange theory should treat this choice as bearing
profit for the parents. But as most economists and parents will attest, children are expensive. Although there are
many ways to estimate the costs of raising one
child (to age 17, without advanced education,
etc.), inflation-adjusted estimates for raising a middle-class child today are usually above a quarter of a million
dollars. Furthermore, the decline in the norms
regarding filial care of the aged, coupled
with social security and institutional care, make returns to the parents in old age unlikely. Nye (1979) attempts to answer
this question by saying there is a form of
intergenerational norm of reciprocity. You feel
an obligation to pass on what your parent did for you to the succeeding generation. But people who are childless by
choice can pocket the quarter of a million
dollars and seemingly feel little remorse in not
passing on the favor. It may be that having children is not a rational decision.
There is a problem of weighing costs and
rewards. We have previously mentioned that the
salience, or importance, of rewards and costs must be examined to understand a
choice. Of course, theorists


would like to believe that some costs and rewards have
roughly similar value across actors. If this were
not so, then it would be unlikely that we could
develop successful microeconomics. Even the symbols and meaning associated with economic units may be unstable,
however. In our society, there are symbols of
wealth and success. Increasingly, both the
wealthy and the indebted may attain these symbols. These symbols may vary across cohorts and periods. We know of a
very wealthy man who insisted on driving himself
in a 10-year-old vehicle. His offspring all had fancier new cars with
chauffeurs. And the meaning of rewards and costs changes
more drastically once we move our comparisons
to other cultures. In Tikopeia, a man's wealth was based on the number of wives he had. But number of wives did not
just reflect material well-being. Daughters could
be traded for wives, and therefore daughters were a means to
wealth and status.
Turner (1991) argues that exchange theory can be accused
of tautological reasoning. In essence, a tautology exists when terms are all defined by one another and there is no possibility of
disproving the statements. Turner argues that
reward is defined as that which is valued
by the person. The choice that a person makes is the maximization of profit. Thus, all actions are rewarding and
the reason we undertake an action is that it
brings rewards. For example, we may ask,
"Why did Tiffany get married?" Some exchange theorists would answer that Tiffany got married because it was a more
profitable choice than remaining single. But
we may ask, "How do the exchange theorists
know that this maximized Tiffany's profits over remaining single?" If the exchange theorists responded that we
know because people always choose those
behaviors that maximize their profits, then we
have just completed a tautological circle. Turner believes that this circular logic is often found in deductive theories.
We do not disagree that deductive systems can be self-referential and closed
systems of definitions, but we do disagree that deductive scientific theories are
ever like this. Indeed, the hallmark of a
scientific theory (as opposed to a theory in general) is that some of its
concepts are tied to empirical measures. We may define force (f) as f•ma, but we have standard empirical
measures for mass (m) and acceleration (a).
A problem with utilitarian theories is that they
often seem to lack this mooring to the concrete
empirical measurement system.
Conclusion
Despite the criticisms, utilitarian, or
exchange, theory is one of the
most popular social science theories applied to the family. One reason
most popular social science theories applied to the family. One reason
Social Exchange and Choice 57





Sabatelli, R.
M., & Shehan, C. L. (1993). Exchange and resource
theories. In P. Boss, W.
Doherty, R. LaRossa, W. Schumm, & S. Steinmetz (Eds.), Sourcebook of family theories and methods: A contextual
approach (pp. 385-411).
New York: Plenum.

תגובות
הוסף רשומת תגובה